77 Comments

Some questions for discussion:

1. Is courage exclusively masculine?

2. Can women show courage in battle?

3. Do you agree with Aquinas that martyrdom represents ultimate courage?

4. Does not having to take a vow of chastity by itself mean soldiers are softer than knights?

Expand full comment

Hey, here's my opinion (sorry for my broken English I'm from Brazil)

1. Courage is not exlusively masculine but in most cases men have more courage than women regarding risk taking.

2. Women can show courage in the battlefield but it would be only a small share of the female population doing it.

3. For some cultures martyrdom seems to be close to the highest feat of courage (Samurai Seppuku, Islamic Martyrs, etc..) but at the same time they recognize other types of selfless effort like religious enlightenment or absolute devotion to a skill as corageous feats. So I'd say martyrdom is at the top along other behaviours.

4. Being drafted as a soldier and following orders requires courage, but to be a knight one must embody more values. Taking a vow of chastity can be one of those values, not the ultimate I's say.

Expand full comment

1. I read an article by M.R.Johnson where he identifies that men act more according to reason and woman to emotions. Hence, Peter may have denied Christ (despite his love for Him) because it was pragmatic to do so. Yet the woman who followed Jesus did not deny Him and showed more courage as they were more aware of the emotional stakes.

Expand full comment

I wonder if you can trace the stereotype of the military 'grunt' that has pornographic/etc images on his wall in the barracks and goes gun blazing Full Metal Jacket Style, as the shift from Knight to Soldier occurred. Perhaps the stereotype started with a dapper looking redcoat in the 1800s who visited the brothel too much or something, lol.

Expand full comment

This has stimulated an interesting discussion so far. I’ve laid out below some points regarding St Thomas Aquinas’ views on fortitude that I think help to illuminate the discussion.

Aquinas draws an important distinction between “acquired fortitude” and “infused fortitude”. The acquired type is one that we earn for our ourselves (on the battlefield, for example). It demands perseverance, and the sticking of one’s courage to the sticking place. We are “deserving” of the virtue because we built it by ourselves in the circumstances handed to us. By contrast, the infused form is given to us by God. Importantly, we are not “deserving” of this fortitude per se. We are born with it.

Aquinas, as Will points out, places special emphasis in the notion of Christian martyrdom. This is the highest form of fortitude due to its moral and physical components. It demands faith, endurance and physical suffering for God. It requires an excess of acquired fortitude. But, importantly, Aquinas regards the battlefield as an arena of unique importance in which acquired fortitude is fostered and *earned* (I place special emphasis on this word because I think it gets to the essence of courage and valour). He writes:

“Fortitude strengthens a man's mind against the greatest danger, which is that of death. Now fortitude is a virtue; and it is essential to virtue to tend to good; wherefore it is in order to pursue some good that man does not fly from the danger of death. But the dangers of death arising out of sickness, storms at sea, attacks from robbers, and the like, do not seem to come on a man through his pursuing some good. On the other hand, the dangers of death which occur in battle come to man directly on account of some good, because, to wit, he is defending the common good by a just fight.” (ST. II-II.123, a. 5)

The key point here is that the soldier has reached a height of acquired fortitude by virtue of his *pursuing* battle with his foe. This is what sets him apart in Aquinas’ eyes from other types of hero: he seeks his battle; his battle does not seek him. It is not forced upon him.

This point of a soldier actively, intendedly departing on a heroic mission finds expression in the Bible (repeatedly) also:

‘And I heard the voice of the Lord saying, “Whom shall I send, and who will go for us?” Then I said, “Here I am! Send me.”’ — Isaiah 6:8

It is this deliberative element to the soldier that sets him apart from, say, the woman that (very courageously) fights a crocodile to retrieve her child. Her fight was forced upon her. And likewise, people will act courageously when faced with a moral dilemma at work or in the community. But the true martyr by Aquinas’ lights seeks after a fight that was not necessarily his to begin with. Similar deliberative courage can be achieved via other means (speaking out against tyranny when others are persecuted, for example); but the battlefield is the most pressing example because it involves intended, preemptive action - from a starting position of total safety and comfort - and obvious danger and terror. This seems to speak to the heart of why a soldier - in all times, in all cultures and in all places - is regarded as a noble and tragic-heroic figure.

This form of martyrdom reaches an apex when it is aligned to a specifically Christian cause. Thus the case of the Templar Knights is exceptional, as Will observes. But Aquinas here points to something more general in the soldier’s nobility: the defence of the “common good”. The nobility and depth of his fortitude resides in the fact that the fight is on behalf of the community - or “the country” as we conceive it in modern times.

But a key question that was raised in the debate was the relationship between the cause of the war and the nobility of the soldier that fights it. I’ll give one brief example that I think illustrates why, even in this age of liberal military intervention, the moral core of the modern soldier remains intact, and why he deserves our respect, particularly from those that have not served and endured his privations (or acquired his fortitude) with him.

Vietnam was fought to prevent the growth of the West’s ideological enemies. It was a dirty, bloody, tragic war. But many US soldiers that fought believed they were fighting for good. Take a young man called Karl Marlantes, who wrote some of the most outstanding memoirs of the period following his time as a platoon commander in the Marine Corps. He was the Rhodes Scholar at Oxford, and forfeited his place in order to fight. His reasoning was that his privilege should not disbar him from serving alongside the poorest of his nation. I regard that selflessness, despite the moral difficulties of the conflict, as a shining modern example of Aquinas’ criterion above. He *pursued* danger for a cause he believed to be noble. He might have been *intellectually* mistaken regarding the moral worth of the cause. But his heart was noble. He left (abnormal) comfort and privilege for the jungle and death and hardship. And he lives to this day with the pain of knowing that some tactical decisions he made in the moment led directly to the deaths of some of his men. This here is the essential dignity and nobility of the modern soldier. And I believe that we should be very careful about we speak of these great men.

And likewise, many American and British young men watched 3,000 people murdered on the streets of Manhattan and felt a similar urge to defend their civilisation. We can look back and see folly in these conflicts. But is unreasonable and, I think, sanctimonious to claim that these men fought and died because they wanted to impose the worst and most recent excesses of woke dogma on foreign peoples.

The modern soldier does not choose the time or the place or the cause - and this is true of most soldiers, including those of the Middle Ages and Antiquity. He chooses only service in the name of his civilisation and his people. He can only hope to fight for what truly is the common good.

But, on the battlefield, he ultimately lays down his life for his friends, which Christ acknowledged to be the greatest love a man can bear. This is the common thread of nobility that unites the men of Thermopylae with the men of the Wars of the Roses, the Somme, D Day, and Helmand.

The soldier - in all times and for all causes - departs the comforts of home for the hardships of battle, and in so doing fulfils Aquinas’ criterion for the highest of acquired fortitudes. The nobility of the cause might increase the moral purity of the fortitude; but the fortitude is incorrigibly high in any event.

I was going to discuss the masculinity element further, and explain why I believe battlefield combat to be the realm of the man (as opposed to the woman); but this will turn into ‘War and Peace’ if I do!

I’d be interested to hear counterarguments to, or thoughts on, the above. Thanks.

Expand full comment

Everything you say about soldiers here applies also to, for example, Nazi or Soviet soldiers.

And it is in principle achievable (and has been achieved) by women, too. At most, then, being a soldier proves only courage, not masculinity (since courage isn't exclusively masculine).

Ultimately, knights and soldiers differ in kind, not degree.

Expand full comment

As I say, the point about women and combat demands totally separate treatment. If I have time I’ll treat it in depth later; but I think that, *even if it were true*, it does much less work to undermine the quintessentially male properties of war than we might imagine - much as a man getting pregnant (if such a thing were to happen) would not diminish the quintessential femininity of pregnancy.

But, yes: Nazi soldiers still met, in a sense, Aquinas’ definition of acquired fortitude. Due to the moral wrongness of their cause, our soldiers met it to a higher standard. Aquinas does not seem to think that only imagining yourself to be fighting for a common good overrules the acquisition of fortitude.

The key point is that there is something about the battlefield - and the *choice* to enter it - that Aquinas recognises as imbuing a unique level of acquired fortitude. He does not say that this needs to be in the mould of a Templar Knight. The cause and cultural aspects no doubt purify the moral worth of the warrior (as I acknowledge above). Hence, it does seem to be *degree* and not kind that is going on here. Otherwise, there are no Zulu warriors, no Spartan warriors, no Roman warriors. There are only Templar warriors. The men of the Wars of the Roses fought, they believed, with God at their backs. But they do not satisfy your requirements either. Perhaps this is what you mean - I’m not sure. But then the term “warrior” becomes merely a synonym for Templar Knight. But that is not what the word “warrior” means. It is a broadly applicable term for men of all castes and creeds that fight honourably for their homeland.

Hence, I think it is useful to recognise this fundamental distinction between the morality of a cause and the acquired fortitude of a soldier/warrior. (Incidentally, I think “paladin” - a word now barely in use - is the best term for a noble fighter.) And this is recognised throughout warfare, too, in the respect afforded to one’s enemy as a warrior. I think there are unhelpful games of language going on here that muddy the waters.

A false distinction has been drawn - one which uses the moral aspects of a particular type of fighter to warp the meaning of a term out of recognition.

The following seems reasonable to me:

“Of all paladins in warfare, the Templar Knights exhibited the highest order of chivalry. As such, they have eclipsed other paladins from all ages.”

That’s fine. Somebody has to be top. But there’s a conjuring trick going on when it is claimed that the *hardness* of men in war changes in kind from one set of fighters to the next. War is war. Men have faced tougher battlefields than the Templar Knights did.

It seems to me that it is more useful to simply state, in plain English, that the Templars were highly chivalrous and codified some moral component that was since lost. But this odd, unproven distinction between hard/soft, soldier/warrior distorts to the point of meaninglessness our most rudimentary concepts of warfare and honour.

Expand full comment

The problem here is there is nothing quintessentially male about war at all. And there isn't even anything unique in kind about courage shown in battle. In fact, a female martyr shows greater courage than a male soldier.

A man getting pregnant is impossible by definition. A female warrior is not.

Expand full comment

But there is something quintessentially male about war - it is practiced in every culture, in every time and in every place *by men* - and specifically not by women.

In theory, a woman can enjoin in war. This, like the male pregnancy, does not overrule the essence of the property.

Refuting this requires arguing that there are no male or female properties that pertain to behaviours/actions. When you accuse a man of being effeminate, to what can this possibly refer if there are not female behaviours? And the fact that small numbers of men show that same behaviour does not undermine their quintessential femininity.

Expand full comment

Women have fought in wars. And effeminate doesn't mean feminine.

Expand full comment

Ok. But I am disputing the fact that, *even if that was true*, it would not rescind the fact of war being the domain of the male, and a male behaviour/property. So restating that women have fought in wars (which I don’t accept - but this present discussion, for brevity, gets us to the heart of the matter faster) does not rebut the point.

Effeminate means a man displaying characteristics that are associated with a woman. So take behaviour x that we both agree is feminine. Many men will also do x. This does not rescind the quintessential femininity of x.

The same applies with war.

Expand full comment

I think the fundamental problem for your argument is that is rests upon conjuring tricks, or at least false distinctions, of language and properties. I don’t mean to say that you are trying to deceive anyone; I just mean that there is an insoluble incoherence in there.

Expand full comment

There is no problem with my argument. The problem is your understanding of what a man is.

You want to say war means a special kind of courage that means manhood. But not even Aristotle, despite being a pagan, thinks courage is exclusively male.

And Aquinas considers "death in battle" to also apply to civic heroes. The acquired/infused fortitude distinction is irrelevant because he also thinks infused fortitude can find expression in military deeds.

Expand full comment

But the thought-experiment demonstrates that *even if* a man became pregnant, pregnancy would remain feminine in kind. Pregnancy would remain *so overwhelmingly* female that it could only be categorised as being of the feminine and not of masculine. Likewise, if a woman (magically) grew a penis, this would not negate the quintessential maleness of penises. Minor exceptions do not negate the generality of a property or category. The virgin birth did not negate the fact that men must impregnate women, for example.

Again, I come back to our most basic concepts. Poll people in the street as to whether war is masculine or feminine. There is no doubt which answer would be returned.

What’s your view on my point about the language of the word “warrior”? Was there such a thing as a Spartan warrior?

Expand full comment

This is nonsensical. It's like saying "even if a triangle had 4 sides".

Expand full comment

But this is the essence of a thought-experiment - you challenge a notion using the extreme example. A 4-sided triangle is logically impossible. A person with a penis that is not a man is not logically impossible (somebody born with both male/female properties, albeit extremely rare). Hermaphrodites do not de-categorise male and female physical properties. Yet they are examples of non-males/females possessing those properties. The same applies with male/female behaviours. The particular exception does not negate the generality of the property.

Expand full comment

As an illustrator I sometimes wonder if my pursuit is a masculine one. However, it is certainly true that many men in more "masculine" professions are degenerate. My take away is that the pursuit of masculinity begins and ends in the soul.

Expand full comment

It is the maintenance of intelligence that is most important. We think it is a 'given' so we neglect it. Intelligence is immediate, but the authority of time is always growing.....

Expand full comment

Courage is definitely not exclusively masculine. Yes martyrdom represents ultimate courage. Facing death in righteousness and peacefully can be more courageous than fighting. Woman absolutely do show aggressive courage, though it's not as commonplace in adult women. Pre-pubescent girls can be incredibly aggressive and by far out-fight the boys. But an aggressive girl stands out because there is less low-level physical aggression from girls overall.

Expand full comment

Aquinas says martyrdom involves greater courage than aggression in battle does because it tests endurance more. Arguably, childbirth involves courage, too.

You're right girls tend to avoid physical aggression as they reach puberty and beyond. This is because they're mainly worried about their sexual reputation, and you can't prove chastity in a fight.

Society heavily conditions boys to cultivate courage because it needs them to fight: biologically, they're more expendable than women are. But because the protector role isn't exclusively masculine and courage isn't either, we can't say courage in battle is essentially masculine.

Christianity teaches that both sexes are in a spiritual battle against the Devil, and this is ultimately a greater test of virtue, including fortitude or courage, than any physical battle.

Expand full comment

Sadly I can't agree about childbirth, much as I wish I could. Any kind of character can let a baby out. But bearing a child that you do not want or cannot raise instead of aborting- that's courageous.

Expand full comment

The point is childbirth means risking death. Historically, the risk was much greater than it is now, but the risk is still there even now.

Expand full comment

I’d be interested for you to watch this and contemplate it’s veracity, Sir Knowland.

https://m.youtube.com/watch?v=hDx2kiLcyqU&t=2732s

I think it’s right down your street.

Expand full comment

We have writings of Paul from 48 AD, and creeds from earlier (Gary Habermas has linked it to within the year of Jesus's crucifixion). The New Testament and the Holy tradition were not fiction written after 70AD as claimed.

Expand full comment

"The essence of manhood is the potential for fatherhood", "No woman has the potential for fatherhood. All men do.". If that is the case, then why a need for rites of passage into manhood? Wouldn't manhood be acquired when a boy enters puberty and is fertile? By this logic, the potential for motherhood or giving birth would be the essence of femininity. "Achilles lost his temper and was effeminate in many ways". What could be essentially effeminate about Achilles? He could never give birth, so he could never be feminine in that sense. If courage is not a masculine virtue because women can also be courageous, then none of the traits displayed by Achilles could be considered feminine, because he, as a man, displayed them. It seems that by that definition, a virtue or trait is only feminine or masculine if only attained, displayed or potentially achieved by virtue of their biological sex. But I would then circle back to the discussion about rites of passage into manhood. It seems that through history, manhood is something that is earned, not born into. How do we reconcile both these ideas?

Expand full comment

The rite of passage is part of the process of actualising the potential. Masculinity is partly socially constructed because society encourages the virtues that men need as fathers.

These include fortitude (or courage), but that isn't exclusively masculine since women also show it. Really, there are no *male* virtues. Men and women *inflect* the *same* virtues differently.

And effeminacy isn't womanhood: it's the inordinate attachment to pleasure and letting emotions override reason (e.g., Achilles losing his temper, a kind of weakness).

So why aren't there female rites of passage? Ultimately, it's probably because women are more valuable as they since they're the limiting factor in reproduction.

Expand full comment